00_PASP.tex
44.4 KB
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
\documentclass{beamer}
%------------------------------------------
\usecolortheme{rose}
%------------------------------------------
\useinnertheme{circles}
%------------------------------------------
\setbeamertemplate{navigation symbols}{}
%------------------------------------------
\AtBeginSection{
\begin{frame}<beamer>\small
\tableofcontents[currentsection,subsectionstyle=shaded/shaded/hide]
\end{frame}
}
%------------------------------------------
\AtBeginSubsection{
\begin{frame}<beamer>\small
\tableofcontents[
currentsection,sectionstyle=shaded/shaded,
currentsubsection,subsectionstyle=show/shaded/hide]
\end{frame}
}
%------------------------------------------
\usepackage[overridenote]{pdfpc}
\usepackage{tikz}
\usetikzlibrary{
% shapes,
% arrows,
% backgrounds,
positioning,
}
\tikzset{
sm/.style={
rectangle,
rounded corners,
fill=teal!10,
align=center,
minimum height=1.5em,
},
sup/.style={
rectangle,
rounded corners,
fill=blue!10,
align=center,
minimum height=1.5em,
},
sub/.style={
rectangle,
rounded corners,
fill=red!10,
align=center,
minimum height=1.5em,
},
ind/.style={
align=center,
minimum height=1.5em,
},
}
\usepackage[T1]{fontenc}
\usepackage{hyperref}
\hypersetup{%
colorlinks=true,
allcolors=blue,
}
\usepackage{commath}
\usepackage{amssymb}
%
% Local commands
%
\newcommand{\todo}[1]{{\color{orange}TODO #1}}
\newcommand{\naf}{\ensuremath{\sim\!}}
\newcommand{\larr}{\ensuremath{\leftarrow}}
\newcommand{\at}[1]{\ensuremath{\!\del{#1}}}
\newcommand{\co}[1]{\ensuremath{\overline{#1}}}
\newcommand{\fml}[1]{\ensuremath{{\cal #1}}}
\newcommand{\deft}[1]{\textbf{#1}}
\newcommand{\pset}[1]{\ensuremath{\mathbb{P}\at{#1}}}
\newcommand{\ent}{\ensuremath{\lhd}}
\newcommand{\cset}[2]{\ensuremath{\set{#1,~#2}}}
\newcommand{\langof}[1]{\ensuremath{\fml{L}\at{#1}}}
\newcommand{\uset}[1]{\ensuremath{\left|{#1}\right>}}
\newcommand{\lset}[1]{\ensuremath{\left<{#1}\right|}}
\newcommand{\pr}[1]{\ensuremath{\mathrm{p}\at{#1}}}
\newcommand{\given}{\ensuremath{~\middle|~}}
%
% Identificação deste documento
%
\title{Zugzwang}
\subtitle{Stochastic Adventures in Inductive Logic}
\author{Francisco Coelho}
\institute[\texttt{fc@uevora.pt}]{
Departamento de Informática, Universidade de Évora\\
High Performance Computing Chair\\
NOVA-LINCS
}
\begin{document}
%
\begin{frame}[plain]
\titlepage
\end{frame}
\section{Introduction}
\begin{frame}{Notation and Assumptions}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item $\co{x} = 1 - x$.
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Probabilistic Atomic Choice (PAC):} $x :: a$ defines $a \lor \neg a$ and probabilities $\pr{a} = x, \pr{\neg a} = \co{x}$.
% --------------------------------
\item $\delta a$ denotes $a \lor \neg a$ and $\delta\! \set{x :: a, a \in \fml{A}} = \set{\delta a, a \in \fml{A}}$ for a set of atoms $\fml{A}$.
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Closed World Assumption:} $\naf p \models \neg p$.
% --------------------------------
% \item Probabilistic choices and sub-goals are independent.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{General Setting}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Atoms} $\fml{A}$,
$\overline{\fml{A}} = \cset{\neg a}{a \in \fml{A}}$, and \textbf{literals} $\fml{L} = \fml{A} \cup \co{\fml{A}}$.
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Samples} $z \in \fml{Z} \iff z \subseteq \fml{L}$.
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Events} or \textit{consistent samples} $\fml{E}$ :
$$\fml{E} = \cset{z \in \fml{Z} }{ \forall a \in \fml{A}~\envert{\set{a,\neg a} \cap z} \leq 1}.$$
% --------------------------------
\item \textit{PASP Problem} or \textbf{Specification:} $P = C \land F \land R$ where
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item $C = C_P = \cset{x_i :: a_i }{ i \in 1:n \land a_i \in \fml{A}}$ \textit{pacs}.
% --------------------------------
\item $F = F_P$ \textit{facts}.
% --------------------------------
\item $R = R_P$ \textit{rules}.
% --------------------------------
\item $\fml{A}_P, \fml{Z}_P$ and $\fml{E}_P$: \textit{atoms}, \textit{samples} and \textit{events} of $P$.
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Stable Models} of $P$, $\fml{S} = \fml{S}_P$, are the stable models of $\delta P = \delta C + F + R$.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Distribution Semantics}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Total Choices:} $\Theta = \Theta_C = \Theta_P$ elements are $\theta = \cset{t_c}{c \in C}$ where $c=x::a$ and $t_c$ is $a$ or $\neg a$.
% --------------------------------
%\item For $s\in\fml{S}$ let $\theta_s \subseteq s$ (unique \textit{total choice})
%\item Define $\fml{S}_\theta = \cset{s \in \fml{S}}{\theta \subset s}$.
% --------------------------------
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Total Choice Probability:}
\begin{equation}
\pr{\theta} = \prod_{a \in \theta}x \prod_{\neg a \in \theta}\co{x}.\label{eq:prob.tc}
\end{equation}
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
This is the \emph{distribution semantic} as set by Sato.
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
% --------------------------------
\begin{block}{Problem Statement}
How to \textit{extend} probability from total choices to stable models, events and samples?
\end{block}
% --------------------------------
\begin{quotation}
There's a problem right at extending to stable models.
\end{quotation}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{The Disjunction Case}
% --------------------------------
\begin{exampleblock}{Disjuntion Example}
The specification
% --------------------------------
$$
\begin{aligned}
0.3 :: a &, \cr
b \lor c &\larr a .
\end{aligned}
$$
% --------------------------------
has three stable models,
% --------------------------------
$$
\begin{aligned}
s_1 &= \set{\neg a}, & s_2 &= \set{a, b}, & s_3 &= \set{a, c}.
\end{aligned}
$$
\end{exampleblock}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item\label{prop:unique.ext.tcsm}\textit{Any stable model contains exactly one total choice.~$\blacksquare$}
% --------------------------------
\item $\pr{\set{\neg a}} = 0.7$ is straightforward.
% --------------------------------
\item But, no \textit{informed} choice for $x\in\intcc{0,1}$ in
$$
\begin{aligned}
\pr{\set{a, b}} &= 0.3 x, \cr
\pr{\set{a, c}} &= 0.3 \co{x}.
\end{aligned}
$$
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Lack of Information \& Parametrization}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item The specification \textit{lacks information} to set $x\in\intcc{0,1}$ in
$$
\begin{aligned}
\pr{\set{a, b}} &= 0.3 x, \cr
\pr{\set{a, c}} &= 0.3 \co{x}.
\end{aligned}
$$
\item A \textit{random variable} captures this uncertainty, \alert{assuming} that the stable models are statistically independent:
$$
\begin{aligned}
\pr{\set{\neg a} \given X = x } &= 0.7, \cr
\pr{\set{a, b} \given X = x } &= 0.3 x, \cr
\pr{\set{a, c} \given X = x } &= 0.3 \co{x}.
\end{aligned}
$$
\item Other uncertainties may lead to further conditions:
$$
\pr{s \given X_1 = x_1, \ldots, X_n = x_n }.
$$
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
Reducing \textbf{uncertainty}, \textit{e.g.} setting $X = 0.21$, must result from \textbf{external} sources, since the specification lacks information for further assertions.
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Independence of Stable Models}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
\item[Q:] Why are the stable models assumed statistically independent?
% --------------------------------
\item[A:] Because dependence can be \textit{explicitly} modelled.
% --------------------------------
\item So, it is assumed \textit{intention} of the \textit{modeller} to not explicit express such dependences.
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{For example:} \todo{Some key examples}.
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}%{Main Research Question}
% --------------------------------
A \textit{random variable} captures this uncertainty:
$$
\begin{aligned}
\pr{\set{\neg a} \given X = x } &= 0.7, \cr
\pr{\set{a, b} \given X = x } &= 0.3 x, \cr
\pr{\set{a, c} \given X = x } &= 0.3 \co{x}.
\end{aligned}
$$
% --------------------------------
\begin{block}{Main Research Question}
Can \textit{all} specification uncertainties be neatly expressed as that example?
\end{block}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item Follow ASP syntax; for each case, what are the uncertainty scenarios?
% --------------------------------
\item The disjunction example illustrates one such scenario.
% --------------------------------
\item \textit{Neat} means a function $d: \fml{S} \to \intcc{0, 1}$ such that
$$
\sum_{s\in\fml{S}_\theta} d\at{s} = 1
$$
for each $\theta \in \Theta$.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Leap into Inductive Programming}
% --------------------------------
Given a method that produces a distribution of samples, $p$, from a specification, $P$ and:
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item $Z$, a dataset (of samples).
% --------------------------------
\item $e$, the respective empirical distribution.
% --------------------------------
\item $D$, some probability divergence, \textit{e.g.} Kullback-Leibler.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\begin{block}{Specification Performance \& Inductive Programming}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item $D\at{P} = D\at{e, p}$ is a \textbf{performance} measure of $P$.
% --------------------------------
\item Predictor performance measures, such as accuracy, are common in \textit{Machine Learning} tasks.
% --------------------------------
\item For \textit{Inductive Programming} this performance can be used, \textit{e.g.} as fitness, by algorithms searching for \textbf{optimal specifications of a dataset}.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{block}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\section{Extending Probability to Samples}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Resolution Path}
Prior to \textit{conciliation} with data:
\begin{enumerate}
\item \alert{Hopefully}, \textit{conditional parameters} extend probability from total choices to \textit{standard models}.
\item \textbf{How} to extend it to \textit{events}?
\begin{itemize}
\item $\pr{x} = 0$ for $x$ \textit{excluded} by the specification, including \textit{inconsistent} samples.
\item $\pr{x}$ depends on the $s \in \fml{S}$ that contain/are contained in $x$.
\end{itemize}
\end{enumerate}
\alert{Consider probabilities \textbf{conditional} on the total choice!}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Bounds of Events}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item For $x\in\fml{E}$:
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Lower Models:} $\lset{x} = \cset{s\in \fml{S} }{ s \subseteq x}$.
% --------------------------------
\item \textbf{Upper Models:} $\uset{x} = \cset{s\in \fml{S} }{ x \subseteq s}$.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item\label{prop:lucases} \textbf{Proposition.} Exactly \textit{one} of the following cases takes place:
% --------------------------------
\begin{enumerate}
% --------------------------------
\item\label{prop:lucases.a} $\lset{x} = \set{x} = \uset{x}$ and $x$ is a stable model. Then:
\begin{equation}
\pr{x \given C = \theta_x} = d\at{x}.
\end{equation}
% --------------------------------
\item\label{prop:lucases.b} $\lset{x} \neq \emptyset \land \uset{x} = \emptyset$. Then:
\begin{equation}
\pr{x \given C = \theta_s, s \in \lset{x}} = \prod_{s\in\lset{x}} d\at{s}.
\end{equation}
% --------------------------------
\item\label{prop:lucases.c} $\lset{x} = \emptyset \land \uset{x} \neq \emptyset$. Then:
\begin{equation}
\pr{x \given C = \theta_s, s \in \uset{x}} = \sum_{s\in\uset{x}} d\at{s}.
\end{equation}
% --------------------------------
\item\label{prop:lucases.d} $\lset{x} = \emptyset = \uset{x}$. Then:
\begin{equation}
\pr{x} = 0.
\end{equation}
% --------------------------------
\end{enumerate}
because stable models are \textit{minimal}.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Conditional on Total Choices}
% --------------------------------
\begin{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\item A stable model is entailed by an atomic choice plus the facts and rules of the specification.
\item We express that entailment as a \textit{conditional}. For example:
$$\pr{\set{a,b} \given X = x} = \pr{b \given X = x, \Theta = a}\pr{\theta = a}$$
\item And now $\pr{b \given X = x, \Theta = a} = x$, since $X$ is a proxy for the stable models of the total choice $\theta = a$, we can further.
% --------------------------------
\end{itemize}
% --------------------------------
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Disjunction Example | The Events Lattice}
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzpicture}
% --------------------------------
%\draw [help lines, color=gray!20] grid (11,7);
% --------------------------------
\node at (7, 7) {$\pr{\Theta=a} = 0.3$};
\node at (7, 6) {$x = \pr{S = ab \given \Theta}$};
\node at (7, 5) {$\co{x} = \pr{S \not= ab \given \Theta}$};
\node at (7, 7.5) {$\pr{E = abc \given \Theta} = \pr{S = ab, S = ac \given \Theta }$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [rrect] (sub) at (2, 7) {sub};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ fill=gray!10] (sup) at (3, 7) {sup};
% --------------------------------
% \node (ind) at (4, 7) {ind};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
\node [ sub,
pin=45:\textcolor{violet}{$1$} ]
(E) at (5.5,0) {$\emptyset$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
\node [ sub,
pin=0:\textcolor{blue!75}{$1$} ]
(a) at (1.5,1.5) {$a$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sub,
pin=315:\textcolor{blue!50}{$x$}]
(b) at (0,1.5) {$b$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sub,
pin=315:\textcolor{blue!50}{$\co{x}$}]
(c) at (4.5,1.5) {$c$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ sm,
% pin=270:\textcolor{teal}{$1$}]
% (A) at (8.5,1.5) {$\co{a}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (B) at (9.5, 1.5) {$\co{b}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (C) at (10.5, 1.5) {$\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
\node [ sm,
pin=0:\textcolor{teal}{$x$}]
(ab) at (0,4) {$ab$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sm,
pin=0:\textcolor{teal}{$\co{x}$}]
(ac) at (3,4) {$ac$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (aB) at (1,4) {$a\co{b}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (aC) at (2,4) {$a\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (Ab) at (4,4) {$\co{a}b$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (Ac) at (5,4) {$\co{a}c$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (AB) at (6,4) {$\co{a}\co{b}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (AC) at (7,4) {$\co{a}\co{c}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (bc) at (10,4) {$bc$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (bC) at (11,4) {$b\co{c}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (Bc) at (9.5,3.5) {$\co{b}c$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (BC) at (10.5,3.5) {$\co{b}\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=45:\textcolor{blue!75}{$x\co{x}$}]
(abc) at (1.5,6)
{$abc$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=45:\textcolor{blue!50}{$x$}]
(abC) at (0,6) {$ab\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=45:\textcolor{blue!50}{$\co{x}$}]
(aBc) at (3,6) {$a\co{b}c$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=90:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (aBC) at (5,6) {$a\co{b}\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (Abc) at (7,6) {$\co{a}bc$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=270:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (AbC) at (8,6) {$\co{a}b\co{c}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=270:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (ABc) at (9,6) {$\co{a}\co{b}c$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=270:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
% (ABC) at (10,6) {$\co{a}\co{b}\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
\draw [->] (ab) to [out=270,in=180] (E);
\draw [->] (ab) to [out=270,in=90] (a);
\draw [->] (ab) to [out=270,in=90] (b);
\draw [->] (ab) to [out=90,in=270] (abc);
\draw [->] (ab) to [out=90,in=270] (abC);
%
\draw [->] (ac) to [out=270,in=180] (E);
\draw [->] (ac) to [out=270,in=90] (a);
\draw [->] (ac) to [out=270,in=90] (c);
\draw [->] (ac) to [out=90,in=270] (abc);
\draw [->] (ac) to [out=90,in=270] (aBc);
%
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=270,in=0] (E);
% %
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (Abc);
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (AbC);
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (ABc);
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (ABC);
% %
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (Ab);
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (Ac);
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (AB);
% \draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (AC);
\end{tikzpicture}
\end{center}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}{Disjunction Example | The Events Lattice}
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzpicture}
% --------------------------------
%\draw [help lines, color=gray!20] grid (11,7);
% --------------------------------
\node [sm] (sm) at (5, 7) {$\pr{\Theta=\set{\co{a}}} = \co{0.3}$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [rrect] (sub) at (2, 7) {sub};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ fill=gray!10] (sup) at (3, 7) {sup};
% --------------------------------
% \node (ind) at (4, 7) {ind};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
\node [ sub,
pin=45:\textcolor{violet}{$1$} ]
(E) at (5.5,0) {$\emptyset$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
% \node [ sub,
% pin=270:\textcolor{blue!75}{$1$} ]
% (a) at (1.5,1.5) {$a$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sub,
% pin=270:\textcolor{blue!50}{$x$}]
% (b) at (0,1.5) {$b$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sub,
% pin=270:\textcolor{blue!50}{$\co{x}$}]
(c) at (4.5,1.5) {$c$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sm,
pin=45:\textcolor{teal}{$1$}]
(A) at (8.5,1.5) {$\co{a}$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (B) at (9.5, 1.5) {$\co{b}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (C) at (10.5, 1.5) {$\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
% \node [ sm,
% pin=90:\textcolor{teal}{$x$}]
% (ab) at (0,4) {$ab$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sm,
% pin=90:\textcolor{teal}{$\co{x}$}]
% (ac) at (3,4) {$ac$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (aB) at (1,4) {$a\co{b}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (aC) at (2,4) {$a\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=135:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(Ab) at (4,4) {$\co{a}b$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=135:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(Ac) at (5,4) {$\co{a}c$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=135:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(AB) at (6,4) {$\co{a}\co{b}$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=135:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(AC) at (7,4) {$\co{a}\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (bc) at (10,4) {$bc$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (bC) at (11,4) {$b\co{c}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (Bc) at (9.5,3.5) {$\co{b}c$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=270:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (BC) at (10.5,3.5) {$\co{b}\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!75}{$x\co{x}$}]
% (abc) at (1.5,6)
% {$abc$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!50}{$x$}]
% (abC) at (0,6) {$ab\co{c}$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ sup,
% pin=90:\textcolor{blue!50}{$\co{x}$}]
% (aBc) at (3,6) {$a\co{b}c$};
% % --------------------------------
% \node [ ind,
% pin=90:\textcolor{purple}{$0$}]
% (aBC) at (5,6) {$a\co{b}\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=45:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(Abc) at (7,6) {$\co{a}bc$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=45:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(AbC) at (8,6) {$\co{a}b\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=45:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(ABc) at (9,6) {$\co{a}\co{b}c$};
% --------------------------------
\node [ sup,
pin=45:\textcolor{blue!50}{$1$}]
(ABC) at (10,6) {$\co{a}\co{b}\co{c}$};
% --------------------------------
%
% --------------------------------
% \draw [->] (ab) to [out=270,in=180] (E);
% \draw [->] (ab) to [out=270,in=90] (a);
% \draw [->] (ab) to [out=270,in=90] (b);
% \draw [->] (ab) to [out=90,in=270] (abc);
% \draw [->] (ab) to [out=90,in=270] (abC);
% %
% \draw [->] (ac) to [out=270,in=180] (E);
% \draw [->] (ac) to [out=270,in=90] (a);
% \draw [->] (ac) to [out=270,in=90] (c);
% \draw [->] (ac) to [out=90,in=270] (abc);
% \draw [->] (ac) to [out=90,in=270] (aBc);
%
\draw [->] (A) to [out=270,in=0] (E);
%
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (Abc);
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (AbC);
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (ABc);
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (ABC);
%
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (Ab);
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (Ac);
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (AB);
\draw [->] (A) to [out=90,in=270] (AC);
\end{tikzpicture}
\end{center}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
\begin{itemize}
\item Consider the ASP program $P = C \land F \land R$ with total choices $\Theta $ and stable models $\fml{S}$.
\item Let $d : \fml{S} \to \intcc{0,1}$ such that $\sum_{s\in\fml{S}_\theta} d\at{s} = 1$ for each $\theta \in \Theta$.
\end{itemize}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
For each $z\in\fml{Z}$ only one of the following cases takes place
\begin{enumerate}
\item $z$ is inconsistent. Then \textbf{define}
\begin{equation}
w_d\at{x} = 0.\label{def:w.inconsistent}
\end{equation}
%
\item $z$ is an event and $\lset{z} = \set{z} = \uset{z}$. Then $z$ is a stable model and \textbf{define}
\begin{equation}
w_d\at{z} = w\at{z} = d\at{z} \pr{\theta_z}.\label{eq:prob.sm}
\end{equation}
%
\item $z$ is an event and $\lset{z} \neq \emptyset \land \uset{x} = \emptyset$. Then \textbf{define}
\begin{equation}
w_d\at{z} = \sum_{s \in \lset{z}} w_d\at{s}.\label{def:w.disj}
\end{equation}
%
\item $z$ is an event and $\lset{z} = \emptyset \land \uset{z} \neq \emptyset$. Then \textbf{define}
\begin{equation}
w_d\at{z} = \prod_{s \in \uset{z}} w_d\at{s}.\label{def:w.conj}
\end{equation}
%
\item $z$ is an event and $\lset{z} = \emptyset \land \uset{z} = \emptyset$. Then \textbf{define}
\begin{equation}
w_d\at{z} = 0.\label{def:w.empty}
\end{equation}
\end{enumerate}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
\begin{enumerate}
%
\item The last point defines a ``weight'' function on the samples that depends not only on the total choices and stable models of a PASP but also on a certain function $d$ that must respect some conditions. To simplify the notation we use the subscript in $w_d$ only when necessary.
%
\item At first, it may seem counter-intuitive that $w\at{\emptyset} = \sum_{s\in\fml{S}} w\at{s}$ is the largest ``weight'' in the lattice. But $\emptyset$, as an event, sets zero restrictions on the ``compatible'' stable models. The ``complement'' of $\bot = \emptyset$ is the \emph{maximal inconsistent} sample $\top = \fml{A} \cup \cset{\neg a }{ a \in \fml{A}}$.
%
\item \textbf{We haven't yet defined a probability measure.} To do so we must define a set of samples $\Omega$, a set of events $F\subseteq \pset{\Omega}$ and a function $P:F\to\intcc{0,1}$ such that:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $\pr{E} \in \intcc{0, 1}$ for any $E \in F$.
\item $\pr{\Omega} = 1$.
\item if $E_1 \cap E_2 = \emptyset$ then $\pr{E_1 \cup E_2} = \pr{E_1} + \pr{E_2}$.
\end{enumerate}
%
\item In the following, assume that the stable models are iid.
%
\item Let the sample space $\Omega = \fml{Z}$ and the event space $F = \pset{\Omega}$. Define $Z = \sum_{\zeta\in\fml{Z}} w\at{\zeta}$ and
\begin{equation}
\pr{z} = \frac{w\at{z}}{Z}, z \in \Omega \label{eq:def.prob}
\end{equation}
and
\begin{equation}
\pr{E} = \sum_{x\in E} \pr{x}, E \subseteq \Omega. \label{eq:def.prob.event}
\end{equation}
Now:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $P(E) \in \intcc{0,1}$ results directly from the definitions of $P$ and $w$.
\item $\pr{\Omega} = 1$ also results directly from the definitions.
\item Consider two disjunct events $A, B \subset \Omega \land A \cap B = \emptyset$. Then
$$
\begin{aligned}
\pr{A \cup B} &= \sum_{x \in A \cup B} \pr{x} \cr
&= \sum_{x \in A} \pr{x} + \sum_{x \in B} \pr{x} - \sum_{x \in A \cap B} \pr{x} \cr
&= \sum_{x \in A} \pr{x} + \sum_{x \in B} \pr{x} &\text{because}~A\cap B = \emptyset \cr
&= \pr{A} + \pr{B}.
\end{aligned}
$$
\item So $\del{\Omega = \fml{Z}, F = \pset{\Omega}, P}$ is a probability space. {$\blacksquare$}
\end{enumerate}
\end{enumerate}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\section{Cases \& Examples}
% ================================================================
\subsection{Programs with disjunctive heads}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
Consider the program:
$$
\begin{aligned}
c_1 &= a \lor \neg a, \cr
c_2 &= b \lor c \larr a.
\end{aligned}
$$
This program has two total choices,
$$
\begin{aligned}
\theta_1&= \set{ \neg a }, \cr
\theta_2&= \set{ a }.
\end{aligned}
$$
and three stable models,
$$
\begin{aligned}
s_1 &= \set{ \neg a }, \cr
s_2 &= \set{ a, b }, \cr
s_3 &= \set{ a, c }.
\end{aligned}
$$
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
Suppose that we add an annotation $x :: a$, which entails $\co{x} :: \neg a$. This is enough to get $w\at{s_1} = \co{x}$ but, on the absence of further information, no fixed probability can be assigned to either model $s_2, s_3$ except that the respective sum must be $x$. So, expressing our lack of knowledge using a parameter $d \in \intcc{0, 1}$ we get:
$$
\begin{cases}
w\at{s_1 } = &\co{x}\cr
w\at{s_2 } = &dx\cr
w\at{s_3} = &\co{d}x.
\end{cases}
$$
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
In this diagram:
\begin{itemize}
\item Negations are represented as \emph{e.g.} $\co{a}$ instead of $\neg a$; Stable models are denoted by shaded nodes as \tikz{\node[fill=gray!50] {$ab$}}.
\item Events in $\lset{x}$ are \emph{e.g.} \tikz{\node[ circle] {$a$}} and those in $\uset{x}$ are \emph{e.g.} \tikz{\node[draw] {$\co{a}b$}}. The remaining are simply denoted by \emph{e.g.} \tikz{\node {$a\co{b}$}}.
\item The edges connect stable models with related events. Up arrow indicate links to $\uset{s}$ and down arrows to $\lset{s}$.
\item The \emph{weight propagation} sets:
$$
\begin{aligned}
w\at{abc} &= w\at{ab} w\at{ac} = x^2d\co{d}, \cr
w\at{\co{a}\cdot\cdot} &= w\at{\neg a} = \co{x}, \cr
w\at{a} &= w\at{ab} + w\at{ac} = x(d + \co{d}) = x, \cr
w\at{b} &= w\at{ab} = dx, \cr
w\at{c} &= w\at{ac} = \co{d}x, \cr
w\at{\emptyset} &= w\at{ab} + w\at{ac} + w\at{\neg a} = dx + \co{d}x + \co{x} = 1, \cr
w\at{a\co{b}} &= 0.
\end{aligned}
$$
\item The total weight is
$$
\begin{aligned}
Z &= w\at{abc} + 8 w\at{\co{a}b}\cr
&+ w\at{ab} + w\at{ac} + w\at{\co{a}}\cr
&+ w\at{a}+ w\at{b}+ w\at{c}\cr
&+ w\at{\emptyset}\cr
%
&= - x^{2} d^{2} + x^{2} d + 2 x d - 7 x + 10
\end{aligned}
$$
\item Now, if $x$ has an annotation to \emph{e.g.} $0.3$ we get
$$
Z = - 0.09 d^{2} + 0.69 d + 7.9
$$
\item Now some statistics are possible. For example we get
$$
\pr{abc \mid x = 0.3} = \frac{0.09 d \left(d - 1\right)}{0.09 d^{2} - 0.69 d - 7.9}
$$.
\item This expression can be plotted for $d\in\intcc{0,1}$
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[height=15em]{Pabc_alpha03.pdf}
\end{center}
\item If a data set $E$ entails \emph{e.g.} $\pr{abc \mid E} = 0.0015$ we can numerically solve
$$
\begin{aligned}
\pr{abc \mid x = 0.3} &= \pr{abc \mid E} \cr
\iff\cr
\frac{0.09 d \del{d - 1}}{0.09 d^{2} - 0.69 d - 7.9} &= 0.0015
\end{aligned}
$$
which has two solutions, $d \approx 0.15861$ or $d \approx 0.83138$.
\end{itemize}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\subsection{Non-stratified programs}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
The following LP is non-stratified, because has a cycle with negated arcs:
$$
\begin{aligned}
c_1 &= a\lor \neg a,\cr
c_2 &= b \larr \naf c \land \naf a, \cr
c_3 &= c \larr \naf b.
\end{aligned}
$$
This program has three stable models
$$
\begin{aligned}
s_1 &= \set{ a, c }, \cr
s_2 &= \set{ \neg a, b }, \cr
s_3 &= \set{ \neg a, c }.
\end{aligned}
$$
\end{frame}
\begin{frame}
The disjunctive clause $a\lor\neg a$ defines a set of \textbf{total choices}
$$
\Theta = \set{
\theta_1 = \set{ a },
\theta_2 = \set{ \neg a }
}.
$$
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
Looking into probabilistic events of the program and/or its models, we define $x = \pr{\Theta = \theta_1}\in\intcc{0, 1}$ and $\pr{\Theta = \theta_2} = \co{x}$.
Since $s_1$ is the only stable model that results from $\Theta = \theta_1$, it is natural to extend $\pr{ s_1 } = \pr{\Theta = \theta_1} = x$. However, there is no clear way to assign $\pr{s_2}, \pr{s_3}$ since \emph{both models result from the single total choice} $\Theta = \theta_2$. Clearly,
$$\pr{s_2 \mid \Theta} + \pr{s_3 \mid \Theta} =
\begin{cases}
0 & \text{if}~\Theta = \theta_1\cr
1 & \text{if}~\Theta = \theta_2
\end{cases}
$$
but further assumptions are not supported \emph{a priori}. So let's \textbf{parameterize} the equation above,
$$
\begin{cases}
\pr{s_2 \mid \Theta = \theta_2} = &\beta \in \intcc{0, 1} \cr
\pr{s_3 \mid \Theta = \theta_2} = &\co{\beta},
\end{cases}
$$
in order to explicit our knowledge, or lack of, with numeric values and relations.
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
Now we are able to define the \textbf{joint distribution} of the boolean random variables $A,B,C$:
$$
\begin{array}{cc|l}
A, B, C& P & \text{Obs.}\cr
\hline
a, \neg b, c & x & s_1, \Theta=\theta_1\cr
\neg a, b, \neg c & \co{x}\beta & s_2, \Theta=\theta_2\cr
\neg a, \neg b, c & \co{x}\co{\beta} & s_3, \Theta=\theta_2\cr
\ast & 0&\text{not stable models}
\end{array}
$$
where $x, \beta\in\intcc{0,1}$.
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\section{Conclusions}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
\begin{itemize}
\item We can use the basics of probability theory and logic programming to assign explicit \emph{parameterized} probabilities to the (stable) models of a program.
\item In the covered cases it was possible to define a (parameterized) \emph{family of joint distributions}.
\item How far this approach can cover all the cases on logic programs is (still) an issue \emph{under investigation}.
\item However, it is non-restrictive since \emph{no unusual assumptions are made}.
\end{itemize}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\section*{ASP \& related definitions}
% ================================================================
\begin{frame}
\begin{itemize}
\item An \deft{atom} is $r(t_1, \ldots t_n)$ where
\begin{itemize}
\item $r$ is a $n$-ary predicate symbol and each $t_i$ is a constant or a variable.
\item A \deft{ground atom} has no variables; A \deft{literal} is either an atom $a$ or a negated atom $\neg a$.
\end{itemize}
\item An \deft{ASP Program} is a set of \deft{rules} such as $h_1 \vee \cdots \vee h_m \leftarrow b_1 \wedge \cdots \wedge b_n$.
\begin{itemize}
\item The \deft{head} of this rule is $h_1 \vee \cdots \vee h_m$, the \deft{body} is $b_1 \wedge \cdots \wedge b_n$ and each $b_i$ is a \deft{subgoal}.
\item Each $h_i$ is a literal, each subgoal $b_j$ is a literal or a literal preceded by $\naf\;$ and $m + n > 0$.
\item A \deft{propositional program} has no variables.
\item A \deft{non-disjunctive rule} has $m \leq 1$; A \deft{normal rule} has $m = 1$; A \deft{constraint} has $m = 0$; A \deft{fact} is a normal rule with $n = 0$.
\end{itemize}
\item The \deft{Herbrand base} of a program is the set of ground literals that result from combining all the predicates and constants of the program.
\begin{itemize}
\item An \deft{event} is a consistent subset (\emph{i.e.} doesn't contain $\set{a, \neg a}$) of the Herbrand base.
\item Given an event $I$, a ground literal $a$ is \deft{true}, $I \models a$, if $a \in I$; otherwise the literal is \deft{false}.
\item A ground subgoal, $\naf b$, where $b$ is a ground literal, is \deft{true}, $I \models \naf b$, if $b \not\in I$; otherwise, if $b \in I$, it is \deft{false}.
\item A ground rule $r = h_1 \vee \cdots \vee h_m \leftarrow b_1 \wedge \cdots \wedge b_n$ is \deft{satisfied} by the event $I$, \emph{i.e.} $I \models r$, iff
$$
\forall j \exists i~I \models b_j \implies I \models h_i.
$$
\item A \deft{model} of a program is an event that satisfies all its rules. Denote $\fml{M}_P$ the set of all models of $P$.
\end{itemize}
\item The \deft{dependency graph} of a program is a digraph where:
\begin{itemize}
\item Each grounded atom is a node.
\item For each grounded rule there are edges from the atoms in the body to the atoms in the head.
\item A \deft{negative edge} results from an atom with $\naf\;$; Otherwise it is a \deft{positive edge}.
\item An \deft{acyclic program} has an acyclic dependency graph; A \deft{normal program} has only normal rules; A \deft{definite program} is a normal program that doesn't contains $\neg$ neither $\naf\;$.
\item In the dependency graph of a \deft{stratified program} no cycle contains a negative edge.
\item \textbf{A stratified program has a single minimal model} that assigns either true or false to each atom.
\end{itemize}
\item Every \emph{definite program} has a unique minimal model: its \deft{semantic}.
\item Programs with negation may have no unique minimal model.
\item Given a program $P$ and an event $I$, their \deft{reduct}, $P^I$, is the propositional program that results from
\begin{enumerate}
\item Removing all the rules with $\naf b$ in the body where $b \in I$.
\item Removing all the $\naf b$ subgoals from the remaining rules.
\end{enumerate}
\item A \deft{stable model} (or \deft{answer set}) of the program $P$ is an event $I$ that is the minimal model of the reduct $P^I$.
\item Denote $\fml{S}_P$ the set of all stable models of program $P$. The \deft{semantics} (or \deft{answer sets}) of a program $P$ is the set $\fml{S}_P$.
\begin{itemize}
\item Some programs, such as $a \leftarrow \naf a$, have no stable models.
\item A stable model is an event closed under the rules of the program.
\end{itemize}
\end{itemize}
\end{frame}
% ================================================================
\end{document}